More Marxist critiques of trans ideology

Below are two more Marxist critiques of trans ideology and the assault on women and women’s rights, in particular by the heterosexual males claiming to be lesbians.  As well as more Marxist critiques emerging, there are starting to be more critiques written by gay men and transsexuals, all adding to the materialist critiques undertaken by women who identify as radical feminists and lesbian feminists.

Decoupled from reality

Meet ‘Karen’. This transgender ‘woman’ (ie heterosexual male) was placed in a women’s prison in England, as a convicted rapist, and proceeded to sexually assault an actual female inmate.  Unfortunately, much of the far left has abandoned Marx’s materialism and been acting as enablers for the assault on women’s rights.

Genderist ideology is based on flawed science and worse logic, argues Amanda MacLean

Here are just a few examples of the recent impacts of gender ideology.

The 2019 Boston Marathon has opened its female competition to people who were “assigned male at birth”, even if they have had no hormones or surgery.

Lesbian advocate and tennis star Martina Navratilova has been dropped by an LGBT+ sports organisation for questioning the inclusion of males in women’s elite sports.

In Canada, 16 women beauticians face prosecution for refusing to wax the penis and testicles of someone presenting as a transwoman.

Credit Suisse executive director Phillip (aka Pippa) Bunce – a “proud husband and father”, according to that individual’s Twitter profile – is currently listed at number 21 in the Top 50 Female Champions of Women in Business by out-standing.org, and last year secured a similar accolade from the Financial Times.

Last week, the mainstream media in the UK reported that five clinicians have resigned from the Tavistock Centre over fears that homophobic bullying is causing lesbian and gay children to identify as transgender, leading to what amounts to medical “conversion therapy”.

And ‘Get the L Out’, a lesbian splinter group from the LGBT+ movement, recently released Lesbians at ground zero – a report graphically describing the routine exclusion and harassment of lesbians who refuse to accept transwomen as potential sexual partners.

The left’s response has not been to stand for the rights of lesbians and other women and girls, but, along with every mainstream political party, to suppress debate and to brand anyone who raises concerns or even asks questions with accusations of transphobia, bigotry and, bizarrely, fascism. There is ‘no debate’: trans women are women, trans men are men, non-binary genders are real and valid. To even question these statements, it is claimed, is to threaten the very existence of transgender people.

There is no doubt that transgender people exist: there are many people who are driven to present themselves to society as if they were members of the opposite sex. Some transgender people suffer from the crippling condition of gender dysphoria that can make it psychologically unbearable to recognise themselves, or to be recognised in society, as the sex they actually are. Such people have a right to access hormonal and surgical treatments where they are necessary and medically indicated. And, irrespective of whether they have had hormones and surgery or not, and whether they have gender dysphoria or not, every individual has the right to wear clothing, adopt mannerisms and perform social roles that make them comfortable and happy. When these traits are commonly associated with members of the opposite sex, they have the right to do so without fear of discrimination, abuse or violence.

Working towards a society that is intolerant of violent and bullying behaviour, rather than cracking down on personal expression, must be part of the socialist programme and will have benefits not just for transgender people, but for women, who are frequently prevented from realising their personal, social, economic and political potential through sexist enforcement of roles and behaviour.

When framed like this, it seems almost inconceivable that the arguments raging on this topic are not primarily between the conservative right and the progressive left, but are largely on the left itself, between gender activists and leftwing feminists. But the heat in the debate comes from the gender ideologists’ hotly contested claim that transwomen are literally women. Not honorary women, or living as if they were women, or like women – as most people have previously understood – but literally women. We are told that transwomen are a type of woman in exactly the same way as black, disabled or lesbian women are. Therefore to exclude transwomen from any women’s service or facility is the moral equivalent of excluding black or disabled women. Indeed, during March, Vancouver Rape Relief Centre, which is open exclusively to women clients, lost its city council funding after transgender campaigner Morgane Oger argued exactly that.

What is ‘woman’?

Was Oger’s successful challenge to the Vancouver Rape Relief Centre justified? That depends what you mean by the word ‘woman’. Or, for that matter, male and female. According to Oger, the biological woman is a myth. Those opposed to Oger insist on the reality of the dictionary definitions: a man is an adult human male, and a woman is an adult human female. But a key part of the gender ideologists’ argument is that a transwoman is a woman, and always has been, irrespective of any surgery or hormone treatment. In other words, a fully intact male is literally a woman if he believes himself to be a woman. This is on the basis of a self-reported ‘gender identity’ that is alleged to be the only reliable indicator of ‘gender’, and is claimed to exist independently of biological sex.

Screen Shot 2019-04-20 at 4.48.39 PM
Melbourne, Australia International Women’s Day 2019 march, an assortment of signs held by transwomen

‘Gender’ here is no longer determined by physical sex, but by an innate feeling of being a man, being a woman or being something else – a non-binary identity not limited to those two choices. Having this innate feeling – a fundamental knowledge of who you are, not linked to bodily sex – is, supposedly, common to everyone. Thus a transwoman claims to have exactly the same feeling of ‘being a woman’ as all women do, and should be accepted as such.

This understanding of ‘gender identity’ was not in the minds of MPs at Westminster when they voted to introduce the Gender Recognition Act (GRA) in 2004. The law was introduced in response to a ruling by the European Court of Human Rights, which stated that it was a breach of human rights to deny transsexuals the right to marry. The obvious conclusion should have been that all adults, irrespective of their sex, should have the right to marry the partner of their choice. But MPs decided that the public was not ready for that step, leaving lesbians and gay men to wait another 10 years for the Equal Marriage Act. However, the GRA was introduced in 2004 in order to allow an estimated 5,000 transsexuals to gain a gender recognition certificate (GRC), allowing them to change the sex marker on their birth certificates. This creates the legal fiction of being the opposite sex, in order to allow them to marry a same-sex partner.

The process of acquiring a GRC involves two years of living ‘in role’ as the desired sex, and a string of medical and psychological assessments – a process of gatekeeping that lobby groups such as Stonewall consider intrusive and humiliating. In response, in 2017 the Tory government announced it wanted to update the GRA to make it easier for transgender people to have their gender recognised through a simple process of self-declaration without any medical gatekeeping. The change in the language from ‘transsexual’ to ‘transgender’ is significant, because it refers to self-declared gender identity, not to physical transition. Some estimates suggest that there are around 500,000 people in the UK who would declare a change of gender, and that many of these people have not gone through physical transition, and do not intend to.

This ideology has sparked off a new women’s movement across the world, opposing the notion that ‘woman’ is just a feeling. Many women see it as threatening hard-won rights that the feminist movement had fought to achieve for decades – particularly the provision of single-sex facilities and services, and political representation. If gender identity, now completely decoupled from the body, trumps sex in all circumstances, then that would give people who they see as men access to women’s shortlists, women’s awards, women’s refuges, women’s prisons, women’s toilets and women’s changing rooms. With sexual assault and harassment from males being everyday occurrences, many see self-declaration of gender identity as a threat.

And if any man can declare himself to be a woman, then what does the word ‘woman’ even mean? The debate has turned nasty, particularly online. Lesbians who reject trans partners are condemned as ‘vagina fetishists’; women have been banned from Twitter for statements such as ‘There is no such thing as a female penis’ and, in a worrying move for free speech, there have been a number of cases where hate-incident legislation has led the UK police to phone or visit people in their homes for making similar statements online. To question any part of the genderist ideology is to be branded transphobic, a ‘trans-exclusionary radical feminist’, or TERF. But is biology a TERF too?

Categories

The core of the genderist argument lies in undermining belief in the reality and significance of the traditional male and female categories that are based on the physical sex of the body. This attack on our everyday understanding of the sexes is designed to force the concession that there is no value in distinguishing between people on the basis of their physical sex – because it is, supposedly, a badly flawed concept in the first place. Key to this argument is the existence of a class of intersex people. It is important, therefore, to understand what the evidence is really telling us and I intend to go into it in some detail.

Everyday experience – and ‘high school biology’ – tell us that there are only two sexes: male and female. But recent research, it is claimed, reveals that the boundaries between what we have traditionally thought of as male and female are vague, fuzzy, ill-defined. Even scientists cannot agree on what ‘male’ and ‘female’ really are! In fact, rather than being a neat ‘binary’ with only two discrete categories, sex is now a spectrum. The ‘spectrum of sex’ case is summed up in the news article, ‘Sex redefined’, by science journalist Claire Ainsworth, published in the prestigious journal Nature in 2015. Do these claims stand up to scrutiny?

Ainsworth presents a weird and wonderful kaleidoscope of cases where sex chromosomes, sex hormone profile, sexual anatomy and gonads (ovaries and testes) do not ‘line up’ – that is to say, where individuals deviate from the typical male or typical female combinations of these characteristics. She lays out a linear sex spectrum starting with ‘typical male’ at one end and passing through to ‘typical female’ at the other, via a range of variations known as ‘differences of sex development’ (DSDs – otherwise referred to as intersex conditions). Her case is encapsulated by DSD biologist Arthur Arnold: “… there are intermediate cases that push the limits and ask us to figure out exactly where the dividing line is between males and females … and that’s often a very difficult problem, because sex can be defined a number of ways”; and gender clinician Eric Vilain: “… since there is not one biological parameter that takes over every other parameter, at the end of the day, gender identity seems to be the most reasonable parameter” (my emphasis).

To the lay man, lay woman, or lay non-binary, other-gendered person, this all sounds deeply convincing when their mind has just been completely boggled by the 94-year-old woman with male DNA in her brain and the 70-year-old father of four with a womb. But what Ainsworth fails to do from the start is to explain what we are really talking about when we talk about the sexes. As the zoologist JZ Young says in his introduction to the classic text The life of vertebrates:

“It is splendid to be aware of many details, but only by the synthesis of these can we obtain either adequate means for handling so many data or knowledge of the natures we are studying. In order to know life … we must look beyond the details of individual lives and try to find rules governing all.”

In other words, to understand the natural world as more than a swirling kaleidoscope of endless, confusing variation – as presented by the genderists – it is necessary to step back and look at the general picture, while acknowledging that there will always be some exceptions to any biological rule.

Like many others in the gender debate, Ainsworth plunges directly into a discussion of the complexities and confusions around sex without first defining her terms. In addition, she makes no distinction between the different ways that scientists use the words, ‘sex’, ‘male’ and ‘female’, when they relate to the whole organism, and when they relate to mechanisms within the organism. These are crucial errors.

Reductionist disciplines that look at different parts of organisms – such as genes, tissues, physiology or neurobiology – use the words ‘male’ and ‘female’ as shorthand for ‘of males/females’ or ‘typical of males/females’. We identify traits like chromosomes or hormone profiles as typical of male or female by first dividing the population into male or female categories on the basis of other characteristics. Having made that distinction, we can then compare the two groups and ask questions about how and why they differ. Thus, the reason we call the XX chromosome combination ‘female’ and XY ‘male’ is because each genotype usually plays an important role in determining the development of male or female anatomy, and thus is very closely associated with those sexes. But the reason we can say this is that we first divided the population into males and females, using other criteria, before checking what chromosomes they had.

To discover what those males and females are, of which XX and XY chromosomes are typical, we look to those scientific disciplines that study whole organisms: their life histories, evolution and behaviour; how they relate to each other and to their environments. Crucially, it is this understanding of the sexes that is most relevant to people in society and in politics, because it concerns itself with whole people and how we interact socially and economically. In ‘whole organism’ disciplines, sex relates to an organism’s potential reproductive role: to produce sperm (male), or to produce ova (female). Evolution has resulted in different body plans that are associated with these roles – we are all familiar with what they are in the human species. Therefore, in any discussion of human beings as individuals, or as social, economic or political groups, in contradiction to Vilain, as quoted above, there is one biological parameter that takes over every other parameter – it is the definition of sex that applies to the whole organism: its potential reproductive function.

Whether it is fulfilled or not, having a reproductive system of the type that produces sperm or gestates a foetus is significant, because it is associated with a whole complex of other characteristics that together have a dramatic effect on life history – particularly, for humans as mammals, the enormous difference in reproductive investment and reproductive risk that can be expected, not least when it comes to the chances of being literally left holding the baby.

Intersex

It is at this stage that the gender ideologists will cry foul and say: what about all those intersex people? So it is worth looking now at the prevalence of intersex, and to ask whether it is justifiable to use it to argue that the categories of male and female are not valid.\

Statistics on the prevalence of intersex are freely bandied about, as the gender argument rages: 4%, 1.7%, 0.02%. For the lay person, it is difficult to know what credibility should be given to these widely varying figures – indeed what they mean at all.

The 4% figure can be immediately discounted – its origins are apocryphal. A 1993 paper by Anne Fausto-Sterling “cited a figure attributed to John Money that the frequency of intersexuality might be as high as 4% of live births, but Money (1993) responded that he never made such a claim”.1

The 1.7% figure, however, has a solid basis: it is the result of a comprehensive review of worldwide scientific literature by Melanie Blackless et al in the American Journal of Human Biology (2000), while the 0.02% represents a subset of the same data. Before delving into that paper further, it is important to understand the definition of ‘intersex’ that it uses. Intersex conditions in this context are defined as deviation from a Platonic ideal of what male or female bodies ‘should’ be like – the paper’s ambition being to demonstrate that sexual characteristics – specifically the size and shape of genitals – vary naturally, just as do body shape, body size and voice timbre; deviation from the norm therefore does not necessitate medical intervention on newborn infants who are unable to give consent to potentially life-changing surgery.

To demonstrate that a significant proportion of humanity deviates from a Platonic ideal is, however, a far cry from proving that there are multiple sexes, or that intersex people are neither male nor female, or that intersex people are a mixture of the two sexes – all claims that the genderists make, based on Blackless et al’s figure.

The bad news for the genderists is that the 1.7% figure does not tell them what they think it does. It certainly does tell us that 1.7% of the human population has to deal with their bodies differing in a significant, and often distressing, way from the ‘norm’ expected for male and female. Where this is apparent to others on a daily basis, they may have to deal with social embarrassment or misunderstanding, intolerance and hostility; and, whether their condition is obvious or not, they may have to wrestle with infertility, or with the lifelong impacts of unnecessary childhood surgery. All of these are serious social and personal issues that require support and understanding. However, differing from the norm for male or female is not the same as being neither male nor female, or being ‘a bit of both’.

Blackless et al compile data on the frequency of a number of intersex conditions in the human population. Some of these conditions do convey what the name ‘intersex’ suggests – a combination of male and female gonads and reproductive anatomy. Blackless et al use the term “true hermaphroditism” to describe the intersex condition, ovotestis – one of the rarest intersex conditions, in which the gonads have a mixture of ovarian and testicular tissue, or where one gonad is an ovary and the other a testis. (Note that the term ‘hermaphrodite’ is now considered outdated and offensive by many.) This condition is very rare, occurring in approximately one in 100,000 live births, or 0.001% of the human population.

Blackless et al list four other conditions that result in either ambiguous genitalia (where it is not clear at birth whether the child is male or female) or a situation where the gonads are male, but the genitalia female in appearance, or vice versa:

 Partial androgen insensitivity syndrome – a very variable condition, affecting 0.00076% of the population. Those affected have testes, and the external genitalia may be atypically male (malformations of the penis, or micro-penis); ambiguous; or atypically female (enlarged clitoris).

 Complete androgen insensitivity syndrome – affecting 0.00760% of humanity, resulting in testes paired with incomplete female anatomy.

 Classic congenital adrenal hyperplasia – occurs in 0.00770% of live births; those affected have ovaries and external male genitalia.

 Idiopathic – 0.00090% have similar features to those described above, but with unknown causes.

The total incidence of these conditions comes to 0.017% of the human population. Adding the figure for ovotestis, we have a total of 0.018% of humanity whose reproductive system may have features common to both sexes. With rounding up, this is the origin of the 0.02% figure.

(Note that Blackless et al do not present figures on two other conditions: 5-alpha reductase deficiency – another variable condition similar to those above; and persistent Mullerian duct syndrome, which can result in normal male anatomy coupled with an incomplete uterus and fallopian tubes. The incidence of these conditions is still unknown, but both are considered rare.)

What is glaringly obvious is that in none of these conditions is there any sign of a sex other than male or female – in this small percentage of humanity, we are still talking about either a mix of male and female features, or atypical male and female features. Nowhere is there a third gamete, or an actual or potential role in reproduction that differs from the two we are already aware of.

In the remaining intersex conditions – which make up the majority of those investigated by Blackless et al – ovaries are always accompanied by female reproductive organs, and only female reproductive organs. Testes are always and only accompanied by male reproductive organs. This means that 99.98% of humans fall clearly into either ‘male’ or ‘female’ sex categories – using the definition that applies to whole organisms, as I have outlined above.

Diverse range

What accounts for the remaining 1.68% of the human population that is intersex? It consists of people with a range of conditions, which are considered intersex because of variations in sex chromosomes, or that arise from hormonal causes. They produce a diverse range of variations in sex characteristics: in males, atypical development of the penis or missing testes; in females, the absence of the womb, a closed vagina, enlarged clitoris or missing ovaries; and in both sexes conditions may result in infertility, a failure to go through puberty, or developing secondary sex characteristics at puberty that are more typical of the other sex. These conditions are often distressing, and some also affect other aspects of metabolism, growth and bone development. But note – those affected by such conditions still fall clearly into the male and female categories, when sex is defined as having a male or female type of reproductive system. Some examples of these conditions will serve for clarification.

First, a large proportion of people with such conditions are women with the condition known as ‘late-onset congenital adrenal hyperplasia’ (1.5% out of the 1.7% of intersex people). These women are born with XX chromosomes, complete female internal and external reproductive system and genitalia, and ovaries. They are female, not male – their body development has clearly followed the female pathway and their potential role in reproduction would only ever involve gestating a foetus, not producing sperm. Nevertheless, late-onset CAH is considered an intersex condition, because sufferers have a hormonal imbalance – an excess of testosterone – that starts to affect them during childhood or puberty and can result in enlargement of the clitoris and excess body hair. Irregular periods and problems with fertility are also common.

While the bodies of late-onset CAH women may deviate from some Platonic ideal of what a woman should look like, and while they have a hormonal profile that is more typical of males than females, it is no more reasonable to argue that they are male, on the basis of excess body hair and high levels of testosterone, than it would be to claim that Ronnie Corbett was female because of his short height.

Similarly, take the case of a woman with Swyer syndrome, who has no ovaries, but otherwise complete female anatomy and secondary sex characteristics. Does it makes sense to turn around and decide that she is ‘really male’ when we find that she has an XY chromosome combination? To use an analogy, imagine that all buildings are constructed with a copy of the blueprint embedded within each brick. Imagine breaking open the bricks from a thatched cottage, and finding the blueprint for a skyscraper within them. Would it be reasonable to declare that the thatched cottage is actually a skyscraper? Of course not – in fact it would be insane. To say that a woman with Swyer syndrome is male would be equally ridiculous. The ‘male’ Y chromosome interfered with the development of her ovaries, but very obviously it did not play the part in building a sexed body that it usually does – it did not make her male. It made her an infertile female, not a third sex.

To sum up, it is by investigating the chromosomal/genetic and hormonal make-up of individuals that we are often able to reach an understanding and explanation of why people have variations in their sexual development. Often, it is because of an unusual chromosomal or hormonal make-up, which may be typical of the opposite sex. But possessing these does not mean you are the opposite sex or are partially so. Most intersex cases involve variations of sexual development within the male or female sex classes. 99.98% of the human population have features of only one or the other class, and not both; and there is no evidence of any third sex class. It should be noted at this point that in an estimated 1% of births, sexual development is atypical; and between 0.05% and 0.07% require an expert to investigate ‘ambiguous genitalia’ that are hard to identify. But a very small penis is still a penis, and is a male reproductive organ; an enlarged clitoris is still a female organ. There are two sexes and only two, and the vast majority of people fit clearly into either one or the other.

At this point, a genderist is likely to throw in the argument that defining male and female, or men and women, according to reproductive function is offensive, degrading or exclusionary, because it (a) reduces people to their genitals/reproductive role and (b) excludes many people who are currently included in those categories. The first of these arguments is truly a red herring – to say that someone has a certain type of body is simply descriptive. It is not to say that that is all their being consists of, or that they must fulfil their potential reproductive function. This is an attempt to invoke the traditional feminist argument that women must not be ‘reduced to’ reproductive functions, without understanding it – the force of the argument is that women’s lives must not be limited to, or by, childbearing or the expectation of it; women must be allowed to play a full and active part in all realms of society.

As for the argument that the definitions are exclusionary, can a man still be considered male if he has had a vasectomy? If a woman has had a hysterectomy, should she no longer be considered female? This argument would, apparently, apply even if the woman involved had borne eight children, and it is at this point that we need to start questioning the validity of applying postmodernist analytical techniques to scientific categorisations. The genderist logic requires that every single member of a group must possess all of the defining features of the group, not just some of them, or we must abandon the original categorisation. Using the same approach, it is possible to argue that the distinction between chimps and humans is arbitrary. Not every chimp has opposable toes (sometimes they are mutilated by opponents), not every human being has language, some humans are born completely covered with body hair, etc, etc – therefore, since we can always find individuals who do not satisfy all the characteristics by which we define the group, we can no longer distinguish between chimpanzees and human beings. Applying such a highly academic and abstract, postmodern take to real-life situations is not necessarily wise – we are likely to encounter several difficulties if we decide that the chimp/human distinction is no longer valid.

Any categorisation in biological sciences always involves generalisation. We recognise that some individuals may be atypical, which is to say that they may not possess all of the characteristics of others in the same group. Nevertheless, that does not preclude them from membership of the group if they share other features. For instance, a three-legged creature that shares a resemblance to members of the group known as ‘dogs’ will be categorised as belonging to that group, even when one of the defining characteristics of a dog is that it has four legs. Similarly, when an adult human being has an incomplete or non-functioning female reproductive system, she still belongs to the group, ‘people with female reproductive systems’ – otherwise known as ‘women’.

Compassionate

The illogical arguments of the gender ideologists are examples of masterful sophistry, designed to baffle the ill-informed with ‘science’, and to persuade the public that a fully formed male is female, and always has been female, solely because he says he is. And the reverse for females making the claim to be male. These claims are on the basis of a subjective, internal feeling of ‘gender identity’, which is sometimes invoked as a manifestation of ‘brain sex’ – ‘the brain of a woman in the body of a man’.

Brain sex is a highly controversial subject in its own right, and splits opinion nearly as much as transgenderism. But, whichever side of the ‘brain sex’ argument is right, it cannot be used to support the argument that a man is a woman. If, when all is said and done, we find that there is no conclusive evidence of significant average differences between the brains of males and females, then clearly there is no basis for the claim of having a man’s brain in a woman’s body, or vice versa. On the other hand, if there is a clear distinction between the two sexes, once again, as for height, you might be unusual for a male, but you would still be unequivocally male, because the criteria for distinguishing between males and females lie elsewhere.

We do not yet know what the root causes of gender dysphoria are. But, if having an evidently male or female body causes you extreme discomfort and distress in social situations, then that is good grounds in itself for society to deal with you compassionately and to make accommodation where it can. We must seek to create a compassionate society that welcomes and supports those suffering from the crippling dysphoria that leads them to seek surgery and manipulate their hormones. It is essential that transgender people are able to survive, thrive and function freely in society without fear of discrimination. It is on that footing that we must approach transgender issues.

But tolerance and understanding of the trans experience will fail if they are based on bad and disingenuous interpretations of science. Trans people are perfectly capable of recognising the reality of biological sex, while having difficulty accepting it on a personal basis. Sound arguments for acceptance can be made without twisting and distorting our understanding of the whole of humanity and indeed the natural world – and there are signs of a trans backlash against the excesses and illogic of the genderists.2

While acknowledging the material reality that there are only two sexes, we must reject the traditional sexist view that self-expression, mannerisms, talents, ambitions and roles in life – other than reproduction itself – must be limited by, or linked to, our biological sex. The fact that much of the left unquestioningly accepts and regurgitates an ideology in which the subjective feelings of the individual trump objectively observable conditions is a sign that we have abandoned the physical, material reality on which our politics is based, and replaced it with a subjective individualism that is alien to any class-based analysis.

Sex is still one of the major axes of oppression globally: female foetuses are selectively aborted because of it, women are enslaved and trafficked into prostitution because of it, girls’ genitals are mutilated and sewn together because of it, girls in poverty are denied education because of it. The Chibok schoolgirls were not asked how they identified before being abducted and raped. Without acknowledging the reality of sex, it is impossible to even name sexism, never mind understand or defeat it.

The left must stop pretending that sex neither exists nor matters. The biological woman is not a myth – she is real, she is here – and she is angry.

Notes
1. American Journal of Human Biology: https://docplayer.net/34440-How-sexually-dimorphic-are-we-review-and-synthesis.html.
2. See, for instance, https://transrational.co.uk.↩

The article above is taken from this week’s issue of the British-based Weekly Worker, see here

 

Flaws of Postmodern Feminism in relation to gender

by Emily Eisner

Since the publication of Judith Butler’s seminal Gender Trouble in 1990, the veritable postmodern third-wave “queer” feminism has taken firm hold of the progressive (read: formally educated) Western consciousness. [16] Briefly, what is postmodern queer feminism? While some describe this branch of feminism as “postmodern,” the mainstream movement calls itself “queer” and thus I will use either label to describe it. Firstly, queer feminism redefines the radical feminist definition of gender to mean a personal identity, or a self-constructing performance, that fits somewhere along a gender spectrum of masculinity and femininity, instead of the conservative “gender” which is firmly and comfortably situated at either extreme. Second, it seeks to problematize, or perhaps just mystify, the traditional ways of conceiving hierarchy–specifically sexual hierarchy–as well as identify new ones. Queer feminism takes Butler’s postulate that gender is a performance to create a new dichotomy: “cisgender” and “transgender.” “Cis” people feel comfortable with the gender roles and norms that patriarchal culture assigns them according to their sex at birth. They are constantly becoming or performing the gender that patriarchy enforces upon their sex.

Trans people do not seek to subvert the gender roles and stereotypes expected of them and instead perform a gender from across the spectrum, or somewhere in the middle. Masculinity and femininity are taken as value-neutral cultural facts, that combine and vary infinitely among individuals and that have no materialist basis or intrinsic hierarchy. Queer feminists assert that biological sex is a gendered construct of patriarchy, and thus has using it as a basis for defining any oppressed group is essentialist. The cis/trans dichotomy within queer feminism asserts that some cross-sexual segment of the population is comfortable with their gender roles and norms, otherwise known as “cisgender,” and lumps both male and female “cisgender” people together in the same category as oppressors of “trans” or otherwise non-cis or “non-binary” individuals. [17] Queer feminists are not the first by far to claim to move behind binaries. Those who reject binaries rooted in material history, Vladimir Lenin wrote, give in reality “no more than an ideological alibi because in their actual practices, they ‘are continually sliding into idealism and are conducting a steady and incessant struggle against materialism.’” [18] In this way, postmodern “queer” feminism and liberal feminism do more than form a sort of pact in the contemporary Western scene, but, from the Marxist historical materialist perspective (which I will establish as necessary for women’s liberation throughout this piece), postmodern feminism is quite liberal itself. The liberal voluntarism of queer theory is evident through its heavy emphasis on self-selected gender identification as a basis of social position, for example.

On the website queerfeminism.com, one finds a manifesto that declares, among anti-racism and anti-imperialism (but notably not anti-capitalism) an opposition to “strict rules about gender and sexuality that hurt everyone whether male, female, both, or neither,” and the “blaming and shaming of trans people, queer people, prudes, sluts, and anyone who does not fit a narrow and arbitrary body standard.” [19] Feminists not imbued with queer feminist rhetoric would find it shocking that a supposedly feminist website used a misogynistic slur to describe women, immediately after using a homophobic slur to describe anybody who is not straight and compliant with gender norms.

As South African feminist Desiree Lewis wrote:

“Consequently, where it used to be legitimate to argue that the voices and interests of women were paramount in identifying how patriarchal domination marginalised a group on the basis of gender, the current ascendancy of ‘gender’ neutralises power relations and almost implies that the social categorisation and identity of women as women and of men as men is not of key importance. Revealing too is the way that ‘gender activism’ has successively displaced the term ‘feminism’. It as though the radicalism signalled by the latter term was being anaestheticised and patriarchal anxieties about change were being appeased.”[20]

In this quote, Lewis calls into question postmodern feminism’s obfuscation of structural analysis of oppression. She also hints at the connection between the ascendence of this “post-al” feminism and the 1970s threat of a radical movement for women.

Queer feminism’s popularity amongst the young and middle class–in other words, those educated in Gender Studies departments since the 1990s–has created a hegemony of postmodern queer feminism over the public and legal domain and eliminated tools for females to fight against their oppression as females. In this way, queer feminism is a kind of backlash against the politicized feminism of the 60s and 70s rooted in abolishing male supremacy. When men can legitimately claim status as oppressed women within your movement due to their individual gender identities, destroying male supremacy cannot exist as a political objective. In addition to being ecologically incoherent in its assumption of a natural cause of feminine and masculine personalities, “exclusive gender identity is the oppression of natural similarities. It requires repression. . . The division of the sexes has the effect of repressing some of the personality characteristics of virtually everyone, men and women.” [21] The resurgence of support for masculinity and femininity as naturalized concepts, although now detached from any sort of predicative biological origin apart from the mythical brain sex, is a step back for women’s liberation.

Additionally, queer feminism, in claiming gender-non-conformity for itself, falsely accuses radical feminism of supporting and reinforcing gender roles by, for example, asserting that women is synonymous with adult human female. To reinforce its validity as the only feminism against gender roles, queer feminism leads many of its activists to seek external validation for their postmodern theories, mainly from indigenous or non-Western expressions of gender under patriarchy. This ideology, which is rooted in white Western academia of the late 20th and early 21st centuries, identifies gender roles that differ from modern Western gender roles and claims them as queer / trans. It takes gender practices from people around the world, absorbs them under the banner of “trans,” and uses it to further the Western political ideology of postmodern feminism. The colonizing tendency of third-wave queer feminist academic discourse renders it not only a Western problem. It leads to Western queer feminist analysis and rhetoric’s enforcement throughout Western countries and non-Western countries through supranational “development” organizations.

Writing about the formation of a “gender industry” amongst neo-colonialist, neoliberal development in many countries in Africa, Desiree Lewis wrote: “The neoliberal cooption of feminist demands is not, of course, unique to Third World contexts. It is an overwhelming feature of contemporary ostensibly ‘post-feminist’ liberal-democratic societies. The hegemony of global imperialism is increasingly eroding feminism and radical cultural expression and discourses in civil society at an international level.” [22] Her observation of the connection between “post-feminist” discourse and global imperialist capitalism is corroborated by other Marxist feminists, whom I will discuss at length later.

Importantly, postmodern feminism connects to broader postmodern philosophies emergent in the late 20th century that are currently debilitating radical anticapitalist resistance. Mas’ud Zavarzadeh elaborates on this connection, writing that “by announcing the arrival of a new society which is post-production, post-labor, post-ideology, post-white and post-capitalist,” these “post-al” ideologies of the postmodern era “obscure the production practices of capitalism–which is based on the extraction of surplus labor (the source of accumulation of capital).” [23] This is the philosophical and ideological process behind David Harvey’s assertion that neoliberal global capitalism “creates a mode of opposition as a mirror image to itself.” [24] Global neoliberal capitalism has therefore also created a feminism in a mirror image to itself. This process is critical to allow contemporary feminists to understand the economic reason behind the omnipresence of postmodern philosophy in “the institutionalized ‘left’” in this age of neoliberalism. [25] It is also critical for combating it in order to establish a truly threatening, revolutionary alternative to global neoliberal capitalism. In the following chapter, I will further elaborate the connection between feminism and anticapitalist struggle, which will in turn illuminate postmodernism’s negative impact on both.

Postmodern feminism is just one branch of an ideological inundation, coinciding with the implementation of neoliberal economic policies in the 70s and 80s, referred to by some contemporary Marxist philosophers as “post-ality.” “Post-ality, in other words, is a regime of class struggle against the workers” that seeks to question “totalizing” theories based on group or class analysis and definite projects of revolution, in favor of a play-, language-, and body-based philosophy that centers itself on accommodating “difference” between individuals. [26] In “foregrounding the agency of the subject,” postmodern feminism “is in actuality an alibi to divert the subject away from ‘making’ and taking control of the means of making,” otherwise known as production, and towards “the ultimate form of post-al resistance, ‘making do’: working within the system and with what the system provides rather than attempting to transform it.” [27] This is why postmodern feminism, post-al anticapitalism, post-al antiracism, etc are not revolutionary theories and in fact hinder revolutionary development. These ideologies often masquerade as the most radical in their rejection of the “totalization” of Marxism, but in doing so, retain many of the hallmarks of liberal theory. [28] The rebuttal of neoliberal post-al philosophies will continue throughout this piece.

Moving forward, radical feminism sees that all hitherto existing societies have been patriarchal and male supremacist, to varying degrees. It seeks to abolish the categorization of male and female humans into two (or more) genders based on a hierarchical ordering of traits coded as masculine and feminine. A true radical feminism does not seek women’s full integration into every level of the capitalist structure, and does not think that equality before the law will address women’s subordination to men in any society. It questions the context and conditions that women’s choices are made in, and criticizes how the glorification of choice, self-objectification, self-commodification, self-empowerment, and consent conceal the greater coercive forces that influence them. Additionally, radical feminism critiques trans and queer feminism’s embrace of gender and the individual choice to perform whichever gender one desires.

The system of male supremacy comes down hard on non-conforming men and women, as movingly described online by members of the trans community. While switching gender identity may alleviate some problems on an individual level, it is not a political solution. . . it undermines a solution for all, even for the transitioning person, by embracing and reinforcing the cultural, economic and political tracking of “gender” rather than challenging it.[29]

Importantly, radical feminism differs strongly from the conservative right in their critique of transgenderism. Right-wing criticisms of transgenderism originate from a reverence for the male supremacist structure of masculine man who dominates the feminine woman, and the violent need to enforce those behaviors. Importantly, the political Right seeks to “build an alliance between the ruling class and the petit bourgeoisie by suturing their conflicting economic interests through stabilizing cultural values,” which includes patriarchal values. [30] Radical feminists, on the other hand, “look forward to freedom from gender. The ‘freedom for gender’ movement, whatever the intentions of its supporters, is reinforcing the culture and institutions of gender that are oppressing women.” [31] It is not merely criticism of postmodern feminism’s reification of gender that differentiates radical feminism from other strains.

The above is an excerpt from a much longer essay called “Red Feminism in the Age of Neoliberalism”.  It is most of Part 2 (“Radical Feminism Over Liberal & Postmodern Feminisms”).  The essay begins here.  We left the reference numbers in our excerpt, but you will need to go to the original if you want to look at the actual references.

Further reading: Trans ideology is bollocks

2 comments

    • No, he was a factory manager and later an owner. It was something he loathed but continued so he could financially support Marx.

      Like

Comments are closed.